As someone who had a relatively light graduate education in algebra, the import of Yoneda’s lemma in category theory has always eluded me somewhat; the statement and proof are simple enough, but definitely have the “abstract nonsense” flavor that one often ascribes to this part of mathematics, and I struggled to connect it to the more grounded forms of intuition, such as those based on concrete examples, that I was more comfortable with. There is a popular MathOverflow post devoted to this question, with many answers that were helpful to me, but I still felt vaguely dissatisfied. However, recently when pondering the very concrete concept of a polynomial, I managed to accidentally stumble upon a special case of Yoneda’s lemma in action, which clarified this lemma conceptually for me. In the end it was a very simple observation (and would be extremely pedestrian to anyone who works in an algebraic field of mathematics), but as I found this helpful to a non-algebraist such as myself, and I thought I would share it here in case others similarly find it helpful.
In algebra we see a distinction between a polynomial form (also known as a formal polynomial), and a polynomial function, although this distinction is often elided in more concrete applications. A polynomial form in, say, one variable with integer coefficients, is a formal expression of the form
where are coefficients in the integers, and
is an indeterminate: a symbol that is often intended to be interpreted as an integer, real number, complex number, or element of some more general ring
, but is for now a purely formal object. The collection of such polynomial forms is denoted
, and is a commutative ring.
A polynomial form can be interpreted in any ring
(even non-commutative ones) to create a polynomial function
, defined by the formula
for any . This definition (2) looks so similar to the definition (1) that we usually abuse notation and conflate
with
. This conflation is supported by the identity theorem for polynomials, that asserts that if two polynomial forms
agree at an infinite number of (say) complex numbers, thus
for infinitely many
, then they agree
as polynomial forms (i.e., their coefficients match). But this conflation is sometimes dangerous, particularly when working in finite characteristic. For instance:
The above examples show that if one only interprets polynomial forms in a specific ring , then some information about the polynomial could be lost (and some features of the polynomial, such as roots, may be “invisible” to that interpretation). But this turns out not to be the case if one considers interpretations in all rings simultaneously, as we shall now discuss.
If are two different rings, then the polynomial functions
and
arising from interpreting a polynomial form
in these two rings are, strictly speaking, different functions. However, they are often closely related to each other. For instance, if
is a subring of
, then
agrees with the restriction of
to
. More generally, if there is a ring homomorphism
from
to
, then
and
are intertwined by the relation
which basically asserts that ring homomorphism respect polynomial operations. Note that the previous observation corresponded to the case when was an inclusion homomorphism. Another example comes from the complex conjugation automorphism
on the complex numbers, in which case (3) asserts the identity
for any polynomial function on the complex numbers, and any complex number
.
What was surprising to me (as someone who had not internalized the Yoneda lemma) was that the converse statement was true: if one had a function associated to every ring
that obeyed the intertwining relation
for every ring homomorphism , then there was a unique polynomial form
such that
for all rings
. This seemed surprising to me because the functions
were a priori arbitrary functions, and as an analyst I would not expect them to have polynomial structure. But the fact that (4) holds for all rings
and all homomorphisms
is in fact rather powerful. As an analyst, I am tempted to proceed by first working with the ring
of complex numbers and taking advantage of the aforementioned identity theorem, but this turns out to be tricky because
does not “talk” to all the other rings
enough, in the sense that there are not always as many ring homomorphisms from
to
as one would like. But there is in fact a more elementary argument that takes advantage of a particularly relevant (and “talkative”) ring to the theory of polynomials, namely the ring
of polynomials themselves. Given any other ring
, and any element
of that ring, there is a unique ring homomorphism
from
to
that maps
to
, namely the evaluation map
that sends a polynomial form to its evaluation at . Applying (4) to this ring homomorphism, and specializing to the element
of
, we conclude that
for any ring and any
. If we then define
to be the formal polynomial
then this identity can be rewritten as
and so we have indeed shown that the family arises from a polynomial form
. Conversely, from the identity
valid for any polynomial form , we see that two polynomial forms
can only generate the same polynomial functions
for all rings
if they are identical as polynomial forms. So the polynomial form
associated to the family
is unique.
We have thus created an identification of form and function: polynomial forms are in one-to-one correspondence with families of functions
obeying the intertwining relation (4). But this identification can be interpreted as a special case of the Yoneda lemma, as follows. There are two categories in play here: the category
of rings (where the morphisms are ring homomorphisms), and the category
of sets (where the morphisms are arbitrary functions). There is an obvious forgetful functor
between these two categories that takes a ring and removes all of the algebraic structure, leaving behind just the underlying set. A collection
of functions (i.e.,
-morphisms) for each
in
that obeys the intertwining relation (4) is precisely the same thing as a natural transformation from the forgetful functor
to itself. So we have identified formal polynomials in
as a set with natural endomorphisms of the forgetful functor:
Informally: polynomial forms are precisely those operations on rings tha